Ecclesiastic Review, April 1847

(Go to Summary of review of Modern Painters I and II, Ecclesiastic Review, April 1847, pp. 212-22.)

The writings of the "Oxford Graduate" on the subject of Art are producing far greater sensation and effect than might be supposed by one who derived his only notions of the changes in the world of literature and taste from what appears concerning them in the most recognized organs of that world: we mean, the leading Reviews. We are not aware that any of these periodicals has dealt either with the volume before us, or that which precede it: unless we except the North British Review, from an excellent article in which we have borrowed the remark just made. The Quarterly and Edinburgh, which seem still to occupy the first rank, rather by force of prescriptive right than from actual and living pre-eminence, have been silent... with respect to.. one of the most remarkable writers that has, for a long time, appeared to challenge their criticism... Writers that adhere to the ordinary and beaten track are easy to comprehend, and therefore easy to criticise... But a revolutionary book - that professes to introduce new truths, to attack established dogmas, to dethrone and break the idols of hereditary taste: this ruffles and insults the 'constituted authorities' of the literary world. (p. 213)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

His extravagance is not the offspring of a fondness for paradox and singularity, but of intense and earnest thought, the fruit of love, and piety, and devotion; and... such a writer should not be captiously criticised, but welcomed, listened to, and cheered on (p. 214)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

It may, however, at all events, for our purposes, be considered as a systematic and progressive treatise upon Art. Starting from the distinction between the painter's intellectual power, and his technical knowledge, - the latter alone of which is his property as an artist, concerned with painting as language, a vehicle of thoughts and ideas, but in itself nothing: he gives as the definition of greatness in Art, 'the conveying to the mind of the spectator the greatest number of the greatest ideas'. (p.215)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

We will first let the author explain for himself his definition of the term 'beautiful.'

ANY material object which can give us pleasure in the simple Con-
templation of its outward qualities without any direct and definite
exertion of the intellect, I call in some way, or in some degree,
beautiful. Why we receive pleasure from some forms and colours,
and not from others, is no more to be asked or answered than why
we like sugar and dislike wormwood. The utmost subtlety of in
vestigation will only lead us to ultimate instincts and principles of
human nature, for which no farther reason can be given than the
simple will of the Deity that we should be so created. We may, in
deed, perceive, as far as we are acquainted with His nature, that we
have been so constructed as, when in a healthy and cultivated state
of mind, to derive pleasure from whatever things are illustrative of
that nature; but we do not receive pleasure from them because they
are illustrative of it, nor from any perception that they are illustrative
of it, but instinctively and necessarily, as we derive sensual pleasure
from the scent of a rose. On these primary principles of our nature,
education and accident operate to an unlimited extent; they may be
cultivated or checked, directed or diverted, gifted by right guidance
with the most acute and faultless sense, or subjected by neglect to
every phase of error and disease. He who has followed up these
natural laws of aversion and desire, rendering them more and more
authoritative by constant obedience, so as to derive pleasure always
from that which God originally intended should give him pleasure,
and who derives the greatest possible sum of pleasure from any given
object, is a man of taste.
This, then, is the real meaning of this disputed word. Perfect
taste is the faculty of receiving the greatest possible pleasure from
those material sources which are attractive to our moral nature in its
purity and perfection. He who receives little pleasure from these
sources, wants taste ; he who receives pleasure from any other
sources, has false or bad taste.
And it is thus that the term " taste" is to be distinguished from
that of "judgment," with which it is constantly confounded. Judg-
ment is a general term, expressing definite action of the intellect,
and applicable to every kind of subject which can be submitted to
it. There may be judgment of congruity, judgment of truth,
judgment of justice, and judgment of difficulty and excellence.
But all these exertions of the intellect are totally distinct from
taste, properly so called, which is the instinctive and instant pre
ferring of one material object to another without any obvious rea
son, except that it is proper to human nature in its perfection so
to do.
Observe, however, I do not mean by excluding direct exertion of
the intellect from ideas of beauty, to assert that beauty has no effect
upon, nor connection with the intellect. All our moral feelings are
so inwoven with our intellectual powers, that we cannot affect the
one without in some degree addressing the other; and in all high
ideas of beauty, it is more than probable that much of the plea
sure depends on delicate and untraceable perceptions of fitness, pro
priety, and relation, which are purely intellectual, and through which
we arrive at our noblest ideas of what is commonly and rightly
called "intellectual beauty." But there is yet no immediate exertion
of the intellect; that is to say, if a person receiving even the noblest
ideas of simple beauty be asked why he likes the object exciting
them, he will not be able to give any distinct reason, nor to trace
in his mind any formed thought, to which he can appeal as a source
of pleasure. He will say that the thing gratifies, fills, hallows, exalts
his mind, but he will not be able to say why, or how. If he can,
and if he can show that he perceives in the object any expression
of distinct thought, he has received more than an idea of beauty
it is an idea of relation[.]
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

Ideas of beauty, then, be it remembered, are the subjects of moral,
but not of intellectual perception. By the investigation of them we
shall be led to the knowledge of the ideal subjects of art[.]
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

Learning and Art are never in their right places until they are in the service of Religion: but they are not Religion herself. But the particular branch of art to which our author has devoted himself has its special dangers from the complexion of the times in which we live. Landscape painting, he says somewhere, has never yet served any moral end, never taught one holy or true lesson, or spoken to the heart of man in the praise of GOD. It is his aim and prayer that it may be taught to do so... But the majority of painters are not like Fra Angelico and Overbeck: and the want of purity of heart in the student of Nature may be punished by his being permitted to bow in sensual adoration of his model. (p.222)

CW

Close