Spectator, 7 December 1844

(Go to Summary of review of Modern Painters I, Spectator, 7 December 1844, pp. 1167-69.)

This is a remarkable book - a treatise on landscape-painting at once intelligible to the general reader and instructive to the artist, written by one who is thoroughly versed in the theory and practice of picture-making. The Oxford Graduate has travelled through some of the finest scenery in Europe, observing the various aspects of nature with a painter's eye and pencil in hand; he has studied the pictures of the great masters in all the principal collections abroad and at home; and his views of the art of landscape-painting are based on philosophy as well as experimental knowledge. His opinions are original, and startling from their novelty and boldness... and though his zeal runs into enthusaism, that frequently carries him beyond the bounds of sober sense and judgment, he is evidently animated by an earnest love of truth. (p.1167)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

It is not to be wondered... that the new doctrine preached by the Oxford Graduate with all the fervour and exaltation of a zealot should have been scouted, without due examination, as heresy and delusion, amounting almost to an hallucination or Tunermania; more especially as the critics are one and all treated by the author with supreme contempt... It were easy, by culling passages that are flighty and extravagant, to throw discredit and ridicule on the author; but leaving this we prefer to inquire dispassionately into the validity of his arguments. (p.1167)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

The root of the matter is found in the following

Painting, or art generally, as such, with all its tech-
nicalities, difficulties, and particular ends, is nothing
but a noble and expressive language, invaluable as the
vehicle of thought, but by itself, nothing. He who
has learned what is commonly considered the whole art
of painting, that is, the art of representing any natural
object faithfully, has as yet only learned the language
by which his thoughts are to be expressed. He has
done just as much towards being that which we ought
to respect as a great painter, as a man who has learned
how to express himself grammatically and melodiously
has towards being a great poet. The language is, in-
deed, more difficult of acquirement in the one case
than in the other, and possesses more power of delight
ing the sense, while it speaks to the intellect, but it is,
nevertheless, nothing more than language, and all
those excellences which are peculiar to the painter as
such, are merely what rhythm, melody, precision and
force are in the words of the orator and the poet, ne-
cessary to their greatness, but not the tests of their
greatness. It is not by the mode of representing and
saying, but by what is represented and said, that the
respective greatness either of the painter or the writer
is to be finally determined.
Speaking with strict propriety, therefore, we should
call a man a great painter only as he excelled in pre-
cision and force in the language of lines, and a great
versifier, as he excelled in precision or force of the
language of words. A great poet would then be a term
strictly, and in precisely the same sense applicable to
both, if warranted by the character of the images or
thoughts which each in their respective languages con-
veyed.
Take, for instance, one of the most perfect poems
or pictures (I use the word as synonymous) which
modern times have seen:-the "Old Shepherd's chief-
mourner."Here the exquisite execution, of the glossy
and crisp hair of the dog, the bright sharp touching of
the green bough beside it, the clear painting of the wood
of the coffin and the folds of the blanket, are language-
language clear and expressive in the highest degree.
But the close pressure of the dog's breast against the
wood, the convulsive clinging of the paws, which has
dragged the blanket off the trestle, the total power
lessness of the head laid, close and motionless, upon its
folds, the fixed and tearful fall of the eye in its utter
hopelessness, the rigidity of repose which marks that
there has been no motion nor change in the trance
of agony since the last blow was struck on the coffin-
lid, the quietness and gloom of the chamber, the spec-
tacles marking the place where the Bible was last
closed, indicating how lonely has been the life-how
unwatched the departure of him who is now laid soli-
tary in his sleep;-these are all thoughts-thoughts by
which the picture is separated at once from hundreds
of equal merit, as far as mere painting goes, by which
it ranks as a work of the highest art, and stamps its
author, not as the neat imitator of the texture of a
skin, or the fold of a drapery, but as the Man of
Mind.
It is not, however, always easy, either in painting or
literature, to determine where the influence of language
stops, and where that of thought begins. Many thoughts
are so dependent upon the language in which they are
clothed, that they would lose half their beauty if otherwise
expressed. But the highest thoughts are those which
are least dependent on language, and the dignity of
any composition and praise to which it is entitled are
in exact proportion to its independency of language or
expression[.]
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

REAL MEANING OF THE TERM 'IMITATION'

Whenever anything looks like what it is not, the
resemblance being so great as nearlyto deceive, we
feel a kind of pleasurable surprise, an agreeable ex-
citement of mind, exactly the same in its nature as
that which we receive from juggling. Whenever we
perceive this in something produced by art, that is to
say, whenever the work is seen to resemble something
which we know it is not, we receive what I call an idea
of imitation. Why such ideas are pleasing, it would
be out of our present purpose to enquire; we only
know that there is no man who does not feel pleasure
in his animal nature from gentle surprise, and that
such surprise can be excited in no more distinct man~
ner than by the evidence that a thing is not what it
appears to be. Now two things are requisite to our
complete and most pleasurable perception of this:
first, that the resemblance be so perfect as to amount to
a deception; secondly, that there be some means of
proving at the same moment that it is a deception.
The most perfect ideas and pleasures of imitation are,
therefore, when one sense is contradicted by another,
both bearing as positive evidence on the subject as
each is capable of alone; as when the eye says a thing
is round, and the finger says it is flat; they are, there-
fore, never felt in so high a degree as in painting,
where appearance of projection, roughness, hair, velvet,
&c. are given with a smooth surface, or in wax-work,
where the first evidence of the senses is perpetually
contradicted by their experience; but the moment we
come to marble, our definition checks us, for a marble
figure does not look like what it is not: it looks like
marble, and like the form of a man, but then it is
marble and it is the form of a man. It does not look
like a man, which it is not, but like the form of a man,
which it is. Form is form, bona fideand actual,
whether in marble or in flesh-not an imitation or re-
semblance of form, but real form. The chalk outline
of the bough of a tree on paper, is not an imitation,
it looks like chalk and paper-not like wood, and that
which it suggests to the mind is not properly said to be
like the form of a bough, it is the form of a bough.
Now, then, we see the limits of an idea of imitation;
it extends only to the sensation of trickery and de-
ception occasioned by a thing being intentionally dif-
ferent from what it seems to be; and the degree of the
pleasure depends on the degree of difference and the
perfection of the resemblance, not on the nature of the
thing resembled. The simple pleasure in the imitation
is precisely of the same degree (if the accuracy be
equal), whether the subject be a Madonna or a lemon
peel.
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

He thus characterizes the chief aim of the old landscape-painters

                                                        [T]he deception of the senses was the
great and first end of all their art. To attain this they paid deep
and serious attention to effects of light and tone, and to, the
exact degree of relief which material objects take against light
and atmosphere; and sacrificing every other truth to these, not
necessarily, but because they required no others for deception, they
succeeded in rendering these particular facts with a fidelity and
force which, in the pictures that have come down to us uninjured,
are as yet unequalled, and never can be surpassed. They painted
their foregrounds with laborious industry, covering them with details
so as to render them deceptive to the ordinary eye, regardless of
beauty or truth in the details themselves; they painted their trees
with careful attention to their pitch of shade against the sky, utterly
regardless of all that is beautiful or essential in the anatomy of
their foliage and boughs: they painted their distances with exquisite
use of transparent colour and aerial tone, totally neglectful of all
facts and forms which nature uses such colour and tone to relieve
and adorn. They had neither love of nature, nor feeling of her
beauty; they looked for her coldest and most common-place effects,
because they were easiest to imitate; and for her most vulgar forms,
because they were most easily to be recognized by the untaught eyes
of those whom alone they could hope to please; they did it, like
the Pharisee of old, to be seen of men, and they had their reward.
They do deceive and delight the unpractised eye ;-they will to all
ages, as long as their colours endure, be the standards of excellence
with all, who, ignorant of nature, claim to be thought learned in
art. And they will to all ages be, to those who have thorough
love and knowledge of the creation which they libel, instructive
proofs of the limited number and low character of the truths which
are necessary, and the accumulated multitude of pure, broad, bold
falsehoods which are admissible in pictures meant only to deceive[.]
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

This is exaggeration almost to untruth; and it may serve to exemplify how the writer vitiates his conclusions by pushing his inferences too far. (p.1168)

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

It is the indefiniteness of his forms and the bad drawing of his figures that most provoke ridicule; for people not being able to make out the meaning of the picture, are apt to regard it as only some smudges of gay colour harmoniously blended. This defect in Turner's pictures is thus ingeniously palliated by his defender, in explaining the rationale of space in the landscape of Rubens and Turner.

[I]f in a painting our foreground is anything, our
distance must be nothing, and vice versa ; for if we represent
our near and distant objects as giving both at once that distinct
image to the eye, which we receive in nature from each, when we
look at them separately;] and if we distinguish them from each
other only by the air-tone; and indistinctness dependent on positive
distance, we violate one of the most essential principles of nature;
we represent that as seen at once which can only be seen by two
separate acts of seeing, and tell a falsehood as gross as if we had
represented four sides of a cubic object visible together.
Now, to this fact and principle, no landscape painter of the old
school, as far as I remember, ever paid the slightest attention.
Finishing their foregrounds clearly and sharply, and with vigorous
impression on the eye, giving even the leaves of their bushes and
grass with perfect edge and shape, they proceeded into the distance
with equal attention to what they could see of its details-they
gave all that the eye can perceive in a distance, when it is fully
and entirely devoted to it, and therefore, though masters of aërial
tone, though employing every expedient that art could supply to
conceal the intersection of lines, though caricaturing the force and
shadow of near objects to throw them close upon the eye, they never
succeeded in truly representing space. Turner introduced a new
era in landscape art, by showing that the foreground might be sunk
for the distance, and that it was possible to express immediate
proximity to the spectator, without giving anything like complete-
ness to the forms of the near objects. This is not done by slurred
or soft lines, observe, (always the sign of vice in art,) but by a
decisive imperfection, a firm, but partial assertion of form, which
the eye feels indeed to be close home to it, and yet cannot rest
upon, nor cling to, nor entirely understand, and from which it is
driven away of necessity, to those parts of distance on which it is
intended to repose. And this principle, originated by Turner,
though fully carried out by him only, has yet been acted on with
judgment and success by several less powerful artists of the English
school[.]
Go to the passage in Modern Painters I

* * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * * *

The benefit that it will impart to the popular taste at this juncture is very great; not merely in opening the public eyes to the merits of Turner's pictures, but in checking a tendency to rigidity and gross materialism in painting, and exalting the spiritual influence of art above its sensual attractions... this able and excellent treatise on landscape painting [is recommended] to all... who desire to have their perceptions of the beauties of nature and their judgment of pictures enlightened, by the observation and reasoning of a writer possessing exact and extensive knowledge of his subject, with refined taste and elevated views. (p.1169)

CW

Close